Skip to content

Boyd on Incarnation

jesus-carrying-the-cross-el-grecoPastor-theologian Greg Boyd has been theologizing about the Incarnation recently. He tips his hand right at the start – he’s going kenoticist.

Boyd’s reasoning, I think, can be illustrated like this. Consider this inconsistent triad:

  1. A fully divine being is essentially omniscient.
  2. A human being is not essentially omniscient.
  3. A fully divine being can be a human being.
  • Why believe 1? Perfect being theology, and arguably, what the Bible reveals about God.
  • Why believe 2? Any human being, it seems, is capable of some degree of ignorance, and so failing to be omniscient. Note that you can affirm 2 and believe that some human actually is omniscient. What 2 says is that a human can’t be essentilly omniscient – such that necessarily, at all times he or she exists, he or she knows all.
  • Why believe 3? The catholic tradition of Incarnation theory, as famously proclaimed at Chalcedon (451).

Boyd thinks 2 is obvious. (I agree.) And he realizes it’s unreasonable to simply declare this a mystery. So, committed to 3, he denies 1. Basically, he revises his understanding of divinity, of what it is to be a monotheistic god, for the sake of incarnation theory. Phoey on perfect being theology.

In my view, this is a bad move. (Also, literally no one made this theological move until the 19th c. – which should worry us a little.) But let me press on.

In his second post, he says a little about why he’s so committed to 3, that he’ll deny 1 because of it.

[Incarnation] doctrine alone is what allows us to claim that God’s eternal nature is revealed in the unsurpassable love that was demonstrated on the cross (I Jn 3:16). If the one who died a human death on the cross was something less than God, then God is something less than unsurpassable love.
I reject both claims here. Jesus is like his Father, and so Jesus’ actions are a guide to the Father’s character. His last sentence here is a non sequitur, and is not taught in the New Testament. (There are surely some speculative assumptions at work here…)
Boyd then goes on to argue that while the NT teaches Jesus to be a real human being, also “the New Testament also clearly teaches us that Jesus is God.” This part is boilerplate catholic apolegetics; Jesus is called “God.” (Boyd ignores the interpretive, translation, and textual problems with the texts he mentions – but hey, it’s a blog post.) Second, Jesus is worshiped.
Wait, stop there. Greg, do you realize what you’re saying? You’re arguing like this:
  1. A being should be worshiped only if it is identical to God.
  2. Jesus should be worshiped.
  3. Therefore, Jesus is God. (1, 2)

A valid argument to be sure. But the conclusion is obviously false, for Jesus and God have differed – on my view, yes, but also on Boyd’s too, or any Christian’s. Whether by “God” you mean the triune God, or (as in the NT) the Father, either way, Jesus has differed from that, and so ain’t that. But Jesus is clearly held out in the NT as an object of worship. So we must deny 1, on the basis of the NT. The Sabbath rule doesn’t hold for us Christians, and neither does 1. It is God who has now exalted him.

I will pass over the rest of Boyd’s case – that Jesus is called “Lord,” is a creator, judge, is called “alpha and omega,” may be prayed to – simply because it doesn’t follow from any of those things (granting them all) either that Jesus is God himself, or that he’s fully divine, or that he’s one-third of the Trinity.

Like many evangelicals, though, Boyd seems to have in mind the first interpretation – that Jesus is numerically identical to God, that he just is God himself.

…by referring to himself as the “I am,” he’s identifying himself with Yahweh who spoke to Moses out of the burning bush saying, “ I am that I am” (Ex. 3:14). His Jewish audience understood exactly what he was claiming for himself, for they immediately picked up stones to stone him for blasphemy (Jn 8:59).

“Fully God” for Boyd, then, seems to mean “is numerically identical to God.” (This is true for many American evangelicals, in my experience.) He thinks this is what the ancient catholic bishops affirmed at Chalcedon… but I’m not so sure! And Boyd agrees – he says in his third post, as many have said, that the Chalcedon document doesn’t really set forth any clear claim about the Incarnation, but only marks boundaries, as it were – tells us things we can’t say about it. Well, the claim that Jesus just is God is perfectly clear, and goes far beyond mere boundary-setting.

Anyway, such a claim is plainly mistaken. If it doesn’t seem self-evident to you that this is false: Jesus just is (is numerically identical to) God yet Jesus has differed from God – I invite you to think a little about the indiscernibility of identicals. Basically, you’re saying that one thing can at one time be and not be a certain way! Having the sense God gave you, you know that any such claim is false. Yes, even in theology.

In his third post Boyd says,

The way most theologians in the church tradition have done this, at least as it concerns the question of Jesus’ knowledge, is often called a “two minds Christology.”
No – the traditional way is baffling claims of “two natures.” That this should be parsed as two minds is a recent idea, expounded by Morris and Swinburne. It is true, though, that from ancient times many were wont to dispatch the difficulty about omniscience with a qua-dodge: “qua (as) human he’s not all knowing but qua (as) divine he is.” It is unclear, of course, how this is more than sweeping the contradiction under a very thin linguistic rug!
In any case, Boyd is skeptical about the traditional sort of view:
To be honest, I have always had trouble rendering this view coherent. It requires us to imagine that Jesus was aware of what was happening with every molecule on every planet in the universe even while he was a zygote in the womb of Mary. And it requires that we imagine this while also affirming that, as a fully human zygote, Jesus was completely devoid of any awareness. Is this a legitimate paradox or an unacceptable contradiction? One could easily argue the latter.

Boyd has a point here – a “mind” in much modern philosophy is a just a self, a thinker, a thinking thing, a person. Jesus is just one of those. (We can’t take the two “natures” to be so many selves.) But then, he can’t, at one time, know all, and not know all – that is a clear contradiction, and so plainly false.

That’s right. But in “two minds” theories of the Incarnation ala Swinburne or Morris, a “mind” is not a self, but rather a power, a faculty of a self. The theory is that the Incarnate Logos (=Jesus) can think in two ways – he has two, somehow separate, sets of beliefs and desires and other mental attitudes. They think the divine mind has perfect access to the human one, but not vice versa. Such theories have their problems – the biggest of which are probably that this is not all the tradition meant to assert (a complaint raised by Boyd’s colleague Tom Belt here), and that they can’t get rid of all the apparent incompatibilities between humanity and divinity. See, e.g. Hick’s discussion of such theories here. (He also has interesting discussion and criticisms of kenosis theories.) Or see Richard Cross’s excellent chapter here.

Print Friendly, PDF & Email

2 thoughts on “Boyd on Incarnation”

  1. Hi Dale,

    I haven’t had a chance to read Boyd’s entire series yet, but I hope to, because I want to see whether/how he addresses the problems with maintaining that a truly human Jesus had *any* of the commonly accepted divine attributes. Once one accepts that a person can’t be omniscient yet limited in knowledge, then it would seem that one should also accept that a person can’t be omnipotent yet limited in power, or omnipresent yet limited in location. Further, once we grant that Jesus was limited in knowledge, it probably follows that he couldn’t have been perfect in love or justice, as those things seem to require complete knowledge to reach perfection.

    I don’t know how any version of a Trinity doctrine survives these problems. If the indiscernibility of identicals rules out possibility that Jesus is God by identity, and the Incarnation rules out the possibility that Jesus is God by nature, then Jesus is neither God by identify nor God by nature. This would mean that he simply isn’t God.

    ~Sean

  2. “…by referring to himself as the ‘I am,’ he’s identifying himself with Yahweh who spoke to Moses out of the burning bush saying, ‘I am that I am’ (Ex. 3:14). His Jewish audience understood exactly what he was claiming for himself, for they immediately picked up stones to stone him for blasphemy (Jn 8:59).”

    There are three problems with that assertion:

    1) God didn’t refer to himself as the “I am” at Ex. 3:14, he referred to himself as the “ho on”, i.e. “the being one” or “the one who exists”.

    2) Jesus doesn’t refer to himself as the “ho on” by saying “ego eimi ho on”, nor does he refer to himself as the “I am” by saying “ego eimi ego eimi”; rather, he uses the copula to say that he existed before Abraham. As K. L. McKay observed: “So the emphatic words used by Jesus in the passages referred to above are perfectly natural in their contexts, and they do not echo the words of Exodus 3:14 in the normally quoted Greek version. Thus they are quite unlikely to have been used in the New Testament to convey the significance, however much the modern English versions of the relevant passages, following the form of the Hebrew words, may suggest it.” (“‘I am in John’s Gospel”, The Expository Times, July 1996, Volume 107, Number 10), p. 303

    3) There is no compelling evidence suggesting that the reason Jesus’ opponents attempted to stone him because he claimed to be God. He claimed to have been in existence since before Abraham was born, and, as McKay points out, “…the claim to have been in existence for so long is in itself a staggering one, quite enough to provoke the crowd’s violent reaction.” (ibid, p 302)

    IMO, it isn’t particularly difficult to figure out what’s going on at John 8:58. The account begins with the attempt on the part of Christ’s opponents to set a trap that would give them an excuse to accuse him. In other words, they were already bent on killing him. Jesus cleverly stymies their witless effort, calls those prideful men sons of Satan, and declares himself to be before Abraham both in time and, by implication, in rank. Such claims could only be heard as false claims by Christ’s opponents, and since Jesus was an agent of God, a speaker of God’s words, so to speak, a lie told by him would have been tantamount to making God a liar. Now *that* would have been blasphemous!

    ~Sean

Comments are closed.