Skip to content

Dealing with Apparent Contradictions: Part 14 – James Anderson’s Paradox in Christian Theology

Man, this is getting to be a long series.

This installment is a book review I’ve written of philosophical theologian James Anderson’s Paradox in Christian Theology: An Analysis of Its Presence, Character, and Epistemic Status. It is forthcoming in the philosophy journal Faith & Philosophy, and is posted by the kind permission of its book review editor Charles Taliaferro.

The review is below. Sorry – it’s written more for philosophy profs than for a general audience. I’ll expand on some of my objections to mysterianism later in this series.

As far as I know, this book is is the all-time most sophisticated, well developed, and plausible defense of the idea that Christians may rationally believe and know apparently contradictory doctrines. Theological literature on “mysteries” is too often marred with unclarity, epistemic carelessness and confusion, and even mystery-mongering, that is, perverse delight in inconsistency (apparent and/or real). In contrast, this book by a philosophically informed and capable young theologian sparkles with Plantingian clarity, sobriety, intellectual honesty, originality, and analytic power (and also, with a lot of Plantingian epistemology, as we’ll see.)

Anderson’s ambitious project cuts against the grain of most contemporary philosophical theology. Consider the following inconsistent triad:

C: If some claim appears after careful reflection to be contradictory I shouldn’t believe it.

O: The orthodox Christian doctrine of X appears after careful reflection to be contradictory.

B: I should believe the orthodox Christian doctrine of X.

What to do in the face of such a conundrum? There are three popular responses.

Most current-day philosophical theologians – or at any rate, many of the most prominent among them – habitually reject O (while affirming C and B), offering some plausible interpretation of X on which X comes out apparently consistent. Anderson, along with probably many theologians and other believers outside the profession of philosophy, rejects this move, as he holds that the reinterpreted X is in fact always out of line with (1) the mainstream of the historic Christian tradition, (2) the ecumenical creeds, rightly interpreted according to the intentions of their framers, and (3) the Bible itself.

A second response is to reject the Orthodox version of doctrine X; that is, reject B (keeping C and O). Theology is inherently conservative, and in keeping with this tendency, Anderson will have none of it, equating it with an abandonment of Christianity.

The third response is to reject C (keeping B and O); this is Anderson’s position, which for lack of a better term I call “mysterian” stance. He attributes adherence to C to “rationalism”, to a prideful preference for our own intuitions over against the clear deliverances of scripture. What is surprising and refreshing is the epistemological sophistication he brings to play in developing and defending this mysterian stance.

The book proceeds as follows. A “paradox” is an apparently contradictory claim. (5-6) The orthodox doctrines of the Trinity and the Incarnation, according to Anderson, are paradoxes. In the second and third chapters he recounts the development of these doctrines in the 4th and 5th centuries, and relentlessly swats away recent attempts to render these doctrines seemingly consistent, by the likes of Barth, Rahner, Cornelius Plantinga, Swinburne, Brown, Martinich, Rea, Brower, Feenstra, Davis, and Morris. He argues that “those interpretations purporting to avoid both paradox and heterodoxy inevitably fail on at least one of the two counts.” (105)

In the fourth chapter he convincingly argues against several alternatives to his mysterian stance: theological anti-realism, anti-deductivism (i.e. qualifying the laws of logic), dialetheism, doctrinal revisionism (i.e. my second response to the inconsistent triad above), what he calls semantic minimalism (claiming that the content of the doctrine in question is too vague to be even apparently contradictory), and the science-inspired theory of “complementarity”.

The long fifth chapter starts with a beautiful exposition of Alvin Plantinga’s epistemology. He locates an ambiguity in the role of the Bible in Plantinga’s epistemology of Christian belief, and suggests some fixes. (181-9) He points out that in Warranted Christian Belief Plantinga is only trying to offer a model of how Christians might be warranted in believing what Plantinga calls “the main lines of the Christian story”. (189-90) Contrary to Anderson, Plantinga assumes that there are orthodox and apparently consistent versions of the Trinity and Incarnation doctrines. (215) Moreover, Plantinga’s “extended A/C” (Aquinas-Calvin) model covers only beliefs based on the explicit content of the Bible, and not creedal doctrines which are (in Anderson’s view) based on the explicit and implicit teachings therein. (190-1, 209) Anderson aims to fill this gap.

Anderson thus extends Plantinga’s theory further, in the fifth and sixth chapters, to cover how Christian beliefs may, if Christianity is true, be warranted, both for sophisticates and for ordinary believers. While this involves some Reformed assumptions about scripture and tradition, Anderson claims that these are not obviously essential to the success of the project. Basically, if Christianity is true, it’s plausible to think that a believer could be warranted in taking the Bible to be a reliable communication from God. And Christian beliefs may be directly or indirectly based on the Bible.

But, comes the objection, if a doctrine appears to be contradictory, shouldn’t that trump its claim to be part of a divine revelation? Even if, say, Chrissy Christian’s belief in the Trinity were warranted, wouldn’t the realization that the doctrine seems contradictory give Chrissy a “defeater” for her trinitarian belief? Anderson takes the bull by the horns here, deploying the whole machinery of undercutting vs. rebutting defeaters, defeater-defeaters, and defeater-insulators. He argues that a warranted belief in divine incomprehensibility will prevent one’s beliefs regarding the Trinity and Incarnation from defeat by one’s belief that they seem inconsistent. (250-6) (More on this crucial point below.)

In the sixth chapter, Anderson gives the heart of his account of our knowledge of “mysteries”, what he calls his RAPT (Rational Affirmation of Paradoxical Theology) theory. He argues that we should take apparent contradictions in orthodox Christian theology to be MACRUEs (Merely Apparent Contradictions Resulting from Unarticulated Equivocation). When we can’t find adequate terms to express some proposition, we’re sometimes driven to assert what appears to be a contradiction, such as “I’m concerned about my wife’s operation, and I’m not concerned about my wife’s operation.” (222) This is a MACRUE, and it in fact expresses a truth, hence a consistent proposition, despite appearances. The equivocation here is in the term “concerned”; he is concerned in that he cares about what happens to his wife, but he’s not concerned in the sense of being worried about the outcome, as he knows the surgeon to be extremely competent. (223)

Here though, as Anderson points out, we can grasp both meanings of “concerned” which constitute the equivocation. But theological cases are more worrisome. One paradox he examines is: “God is one divine being and God is three divine beings.” (226) None of those terms appear equivocal, and yet at least one must be, if that statement is to only appear to express a contradiction. Anderson tries out slapping subscript numbers on various of the terms (e.g. “God is one divine1 being and God is three divine2 beings.”), but that seems ad hoc, and worse, it seems empty – the epitome of a merely formal or verbal solution to a very real difficulty.

Anderson argues that this move isn’t ad hoc because if God is incomprehensible (as nearly all Christians grant), then we should expect apparent contradictions to arise in our thinking and speaking about him. (237-43) Moreover, all of this, Anderson argues, fits well with a doctrine of analogy, in light of which we can see that the disambiguated terms needn’t be devoid of meaning. Rather, they each have a meaning which partially, but not completely, overlaps how we use those terms in ordinary contexts.

In sum, if Christianity were true, we’d expect that Christians would reasonably believe in and know about “mysteries”, where a “mystery” is “a metaphysical state of affairs the revelation of which appears implicitly contradictory to us on account of present limitations in our cognitive apparatus and thus resists systematic description in a perspicuously consistent manner.” (245, original italics) Facts are mysterious in the primary sense, then, and doctrines are mysterious derivatively, insofar as they are about these sorts of facts. (246) Note that Anderson avoids the hard to justify claim that a “mystery” is permanently beyond human capacities. The seventh chapter tangles, somewhat less convincingly, with other objections to his mysterian position on the Trinity and Incarnation, and the eighth chapter briefly summarizes his project and suggests a few implications of it for biblical interpretation and apologetics.

A project this ambitious bristles with difficulties, but here I can only sketch out a central one. Anderson’s project seems to crucially involve the following non sequitur: 1. If God exists, then he’s incomprehensible. 2. Therefore, if God exists, then it’s likely that humans in thinking about God along the lines of God’s self-revelation in the Bible will be forced into apparently contradictory thoughts and statements. The problem is that 2 doesn’t follow from 1, because Anderson’s doctrine of “divine incompehensibility” is just the uncontroversial claim that “although God can be known in part, he cannot be known fully and exhaustively.” (237) That is a very weak claim, to which probably no theist will object. Given our limited information, the probability of God’s putting us in a paradoxical theological situation is inscrutable, not more probable than not. A child may not understand the sexual aspect of her parents’ relationship, but it doesn’t follow that she’ll probably run into paradoxes in thinking about her parents. Whether she does or not depends on her cognitive capacities, on precisely what information her parents choose to reveal, and perhaps on her own free choices concerning how she reflects on her parents’ relationship. It only follows from divine incomprehensibility that we can’t be sure or anything close to it that we’ll never run into paradoxes in theology. Non-mysterians, it seems to me, can happily admit this, and proceed in their non-mysterian ways.

But if we lack the grounds to expect theological paradoxes, then the clear and stable appearance of contradiction seems to provide an undefeated defeater for the warrant and justification of our paradoxical theological claims after all. (Cf. 252) Without a stronger doctrine of incomprehensibility, there’s no way to rule out that our cherished paradoxes have been created by our misguided speculations or wrongheaded scriptural exegesis, rather than being thrust on us by transcendent facts together with our epistemic limits. In sum, it isn’t clear that the mysterian response to my inconsistent triad above fares better than the other two. Would a stronger doctrine of divine incomprehensibility be worth the price?

This book deserves to be widely read by students of theology, philosophy of religion, and apologetics. It is nicely written, organized, and presented, and features a good index, and only very few (insignificant) typographical errors. It would provide ideal material for graduate level seminars in any of the aforementioned fields. Some readers will, like this reviewer, take this book to suggest that the mysterian defense of Christian belief is a philosophical dead end, while others will take it as presenting an exciting, well-motivated, and genuinely different apologetic option. Either way, there’s apt material for reflection here, whether one is trying to come up with a defeater-defeater-defeater, or trying to shore up the mysterian defenses.

Print Friendly, PDF & Email

14 thoughts on “Dealing with Apparent Contradictions: Part 14 – James Anderson’s Paradox in Christian Theology”

  1. Just finished Anderson’s book… and it was indeed incredible.

    But I also had the same intuition that the epistemic probability of encountering paradox given God’s incomprehensibility is inscrutable.

    Also of note, is the suggestion at the very end of the book that a purported revealed paradox is less likely a product of human contrivance than of divine revelation. This reminds me of a move many apologists make in arguing for the historicity of the gospels – that if the gospels were fabricated, you wouldn’t expect apparently conflicting accounts, because fabrication would most naturally display the wit of presenting the data in an apparently non-conflicting way. But while I find that upon reflection and study, the respective paradoxes are easier to diffuse in the case of the gospels, they are assumed to exist even upon careful reflection in Anderson’s accounts of the trinity and incarnation. Why not then, open up the possibility that this apparent contradiction is an actual contradiction – the product of unwitting human mistake? The argument would go:

    1) The apparent contradictions of the trinity and incarnation P are probably either a) the product of human contrivance, b) divine revelation, or c) the product of unwitting human mistake.
    2) P given a) is low.
    3) P given b) is inscrutable.
    4) P given c) is probable.
    Therefore, P is probably the product of unwitting human mistake.

    And if the (Nicene and Chalcedonian) doctrines of the trinity and incarnation are determinants of orthodoxy (and I have doubts as to whether they are), such a conclusion might even constitute a defeater for the whole of Christian faith. Though I’d be curious if there are apologists who would dispute premise 4. A strong defense in this direction might look like the following – try to think of all the ways in which one might suspect the human propagators of P to have honestly but unreliably come to believe or propagated P, and show they were actually rather reliable in those respects. Though since I know that you, Dale, probably already buy something like my argument above, I’d be curious where you think the unwitting human mistake lies. Or do you rather reject premise 2, thinking that Christology became infected with corrupting political agendas and pagan assumptions?

  2. Pingback: trinities - “On Positive Mysterianism” (Dale)

  3. Interesting review. I especially like your observation that paradox stemming from the biblical doctrine of Incomprehensibility is a non sequitur. Of course, your observation is based on the idea that Anderson is operating on the basis of the biblical doctrine of Incomprehensibility (see the Clark/Van Til Controversy).

    I also very much agree with this observation:

    “But if we lack the grounds to expect theological paradoxes, then the clear and stable appearance of contradiction seems to provide an undefeated defeater for the warrant and justification of our paradoxical theological claims after all. (Cf. 252) Without a stronger doctrine of incomprehensibility, there’s no way to rule out that our cherished paradoxes have been created by our misguided speculations or wrongheaded scriptural exegesis, rather than being thrust on us by transcendent facts together with our epistemic limits. In sum, it isn’t clear that the mysterian response to my inconsistent triad above fares better than the other two. Would a stronger doctrine of divine incomprehensibility be worth the price?”

    I would say, no.

  4. Pingback: trinities - Dealing with Apparent Contradictions: Part 17 - More Mysterious Interpretations - Nye’s Vine-Man (Dale)

  5. Pingback: trinities - Dealing with Apparent Contradictions: Part 15 - Positive vs. Negative Mysterianism (Dale)

  6. Dale, thanks for your input on the book. I’ll check it out when I’m able.

    Now let me backtrack a bit to the related topic of implicit faith. I’m wondering if your saw this blog post by Alexander Pruss about two months back: http://alexanderpruss.blogspot.com/2008/06/orthodoxy-and-ordinary-believer.html … I’m glad that he asks, “What about the ordinary believer?” – because, that’s where I’m at. I’m hoping to hear even more about the ordinary believer here at the Trinities blog. I mean, what is a parent supposed to tell their child about the Trinity? That’s my million dollar question. Thanks again for this blog series, keep it going.

  7. I don’t offer anything like a general theory of vagueness in the book, but arguably I do offer “a theory that clearly explains the apparent inconsistencies generated by vague [theological] terms while preserving as much as possible our other a priori commitments, e.g., to classical logic (or most of classical logic).” It’s a theory that tries to do justice to the entire phenomenon of theological paradox, where that paradox arises (in part) from semantic imprecision.

  8. Sorry to be so long in getting back. I took to concept of being a moon to illustrate the fact that many concepts we take to be well-understood are not. This is what happens a fortiori in contexts of perfect beings. I definitely reject embracing mystery in these contexts as essentially admitting defeat. What we should be doing is the very thing we do in all other philosophical contexts where paradox arises. When we discover that vagueness gives rise to sorites paradoxes, we do not just embrace inconsistency nor do we simply deny that there are vague terms. There definitely are. Rather we try to offer theories of vagueness that DO JUSTICE TO THE ENTIRE PHENOMENON of vagueness. We want a theory that clearly explains the apparent inconsistencies generated by vague terms while preserving as much as possible our other a priori commitments, e.g., to classical logic (or most of classical logic).

  9. Hi Mike,

    Not all intuitions are created equal. If I find one wavering, coming and going, changing, then it’s a pretty weak one, and will give me at best a weak reason for concluding things are how it seems (in that intuition), i.e. that doctrine D really is contradictory. I agree that the concept of a moon is somewhat vague.

    The thing is, in philosophy we have no choice but to trust our (firm, steady, clear) intuitions, all the while admitting that we could be mistaken. I’ll be interested to hear where you come down when I distinguish positive from negative mysterianism (yes, it’s an ugly term!) – hopefully within the next few days.

  10. Hi Ryan,

    I think his book is well-written, and it is compartmentalized enough that you don’t need to read it straight through. In the later chapters, he pushed the dialectic between him and me a little further. Also interesting are his comments on why he rejects various of (what I call) rational reconstructions of the Trinity. So don’t be afraid to dip in!

  11. C: If some claim appears after careful reflection to be contradictory I shouldn’t believe it.

    Hi Dale,

    I also take the line of rejecting (C). But I’m not crazy about the ‘mysterian’ appellation. The reason to reject (C) in my view is that many of our intuitions are not especially well-informed, even intuitions concerning common concepts. To borrow an example from Roy Sorensen, take your concept of ‘being a moon’. Pretty common. But it is not difficult to show that we don’t have a clear concept of ‘being a moon’. Suppose Jupiter’s moon, Io, itself acquired a moon. Would the moon of Io be a moon of Jupiter? Who knows? I’ve never considered whether ‘being a moon’ is transitive. But the concept of omnipotence, omniscience and omnibenevolence are much more complicated than the concpet of being a moon. We just have not considered all of the hypothetical contexts which might illuminate these concepts for us. So I’d deny that we know enough about the content of these concepts to trust the deliverances of ‘careful reflection’.

  12. Anderson’s “Paradox in Christian Theology” sounds fascinating. I just read his article “In Defence of Mystery: a reply to Dale Tuggy” and I’m hungry for more. However, I’m wondering if his book would be too rough going for a philosophical dilettante like myself. Anyways, looking forward to part 15 and beyond here.

  13. Pingback: Dale Tuggy vs. James Anderson on mystery « City of God

Comments are closed.