Skip to content

Richard of St. Victor 7 – The Same Divine Substance (Scott)

There is only one.
There is only one.

Up to this point in Book 3 Richard has told us several things about love (caritas). We have wondered at his saying there isn’t a perfectly good person if he doesn’t love. We have sorted through some necessary conditions for love such that we wonder whether a perfectly good person p must love another person q if p is to be perfectly good. You might say we’ve been contemplating some divine ethics, or aesthetics, or whatever.

In the previous post I suggested how we might interpret what Richard means by saying (two) divine persons are equal and similar to one another, namely the divine persons have the same disposition of love and the same acts of love (see [T4’] and [T5’]). In the next part of Richard’s argument he returns to his metaphysics of the divine substance which he discussed in Books 1 and 2. (In the English translation the term ‘plenitudo’ is translated as ‘fullness’, which might be misleading because it is a technical term in contrast with ‘participation’ (participatio). So I stick with ‘plenitude’.) In Book 3.8 Richard reminds us that

R1: In mutually loved and mutually loving persons, in order that supreme love might exist worthily, there must be in each both supreme perfection and the [plenitude] of all perfection.

In Book 1 Richard distinguished between ‘plenitude’ and ‘participation’.

R2: If p has a plenitude of X, then p has X independently of all other substances.

R3: If p has a participation of X, then p has X dependently on another substance.

Think of the plenitude of X as the original X, and participation as contingently having a likeness of X. So,

R4: If each divine person p and q has the plenitude of supreme love, then p and q have supreme love independently of any other substance.

In Book 1 Richard argued that there can be only one substance that is eternal and causally depends on no other substance; all other existing substances are either sempiternal (roughly co-eternal) causally from another substance (e.g., angels), or temporal and causally from another substance (all material creatures); there is no substance that is temporal and not causally from another substance.

Given R1, R2, and R4, it looks like there are two persons that have numerically the same substance. But what level of generality or individuality is this substance? Some (Aristotelian secondary) substances are quite general like animal, and some are quite specific like human. Even still, there are individual humans like Dale, Joseph, and JT. So, on what level ought we to take the divine substance? Well, none of these. Instead, in Book 2.12, which I consider to be one of the most overlooked and under-appreciated sections of Richard’s De Trinitate, he declares that some substances by definition are singular, non-repeatable, non-instantiable (I explain ‘instantiable’ and ‘non-instantiable’ a bit more in the next post). That is, if we consider the person Daniel, he is constituted by the substance Danielitas (Richard borrows from Boethius’s Platonitas). If a person is constituted by Danielitas, then he is the person Daniel. Having made this distinction Richard applies it to the divine substance by calling it divinitas. If a person is constituted by divinitas, then he is a divine person. (I return to the ‘constitution’ issue in the next post.) Notice that divinitas is a substance and there cannot be further instantiations of it. So, the two divine persons (at this point in the argument) have numerically the same singular substance called divinitas.

Next Richard gives us some rhetorical helps. Consider a human person. On Richard’s view she is composed of two substances: a bodily substance and a rational substance, and yet she is one person. Why think it impossible then if in God there is one substance and yet more than one person? Crazier things happen….

“Explain to me, I implore you, how there is personal unity in so great a dissimilitude and diversity of substances, and I will tell you how there is a substantial unity in so great a similitude and equality of [divine] persons. You say, ‘I do not grasp it; I do not understand; but even if the understanding does not grasp it, nevertheless experience itself per suades me.’ Well said indeed and rightly too! But if experience teaches you that something exists in human nature that is above understanding, should it not also have taught you that something exists above your understanding in divine nature? And so a person can learn from himself, by way of opposites as it were, what he ought to think concerning those things which are proposed to him for believing concerning his God.” (Book 3.10)

Before moving on to Richard’s initial argument for why there must be a trinity and not a duality of divine persons based on what he takes as the nature of perfect love I want to mention one hitherto overlooked issue in contemporary Trinitarian discussions. This issue will certainly be discussed after this current series on Book 3 of Richard’s De Trinitate. That is, Richard’s apparent constitutional Latin trinitarianism [= CLT] which I take as a different stream of Latin trinitarianism than the one Brian Leftow has called “a Latin Trinity” or “the Latin Trinity”. I take Richard and those who rightly interpret him or agree with him (e.g., Henry of Ghent and Duns Scotus) to follow CLT, but those who are less interested in Richard’s own view or just misinterpret him to satisfy Leftow’s LT, or what I would call non-constitutional Latin trinitarianism [= NCLT]. If this is right, as I believe it is, then Brower and Rea have some new (non-Dominican) comrades.

2 thoughts on “Richard of St. Victor 7 – The Same Divine Substance (Scott)”

  1. I am reading all of Richard’s non-book 3s in the Latin critical edition.

    In the next post I translate a CLT suggestive text. I remember others– but I’d need to look them up.

  2. Hey guys – I’m fully back to work now, and back in the saddle with Richard, and with these sorts of argument. I just reviewed the whole series so far.

    Some comments:

    I still think the rocket fails to get off the launch pad. Why couldn’t there be a being which is absolutely perfect, and yet which doesn’t enjoy peer love? I see no contradiction whatever there, nor has Richard given us any reason to think this is impossible. Somewhere along the way, Joseph observed that one who is in a loving relationship with another is, all things being equal, better off than one who is not. I agree – this is just to say that there is value in friendship. There is reason, though, to think that God could be well off even without any such good. But I’ll leave that to a paper I’m working on – I’ll either post it, or serialize it at some point here. As I’m set to finish up Richard’s book III, maybe I’ll post my paper immediately after.

    Someone brought up Aelred of Rievaulx – his book Spiritual Friendship is a classic, a very interesting Christian philosophy of friendship. He does at one point suggest in passing almost that “God is friendship”, but doesn’t at all take that in a ST direction. It’s really sort of a practical book, and I don’t detect any interest in perfect being theology in it. More relevant is his analysis of love, which is in his earlier book, the Mirror of Charity. I’ve ordered that book, and will post on it during my part of the series. One thing he’s clear about is that friendship involves more than love. There are countless people whom we must love, and yet there are few, in his view, with whom we ought to be friends. Loving is basically seeking the good of someone, whereas friendship involves that, along with a wonderful but dangerous self-disclosure, or intimacy. I’ll leave it there for now.

    Scott – Where are you reading Richard’s book II? I know we have the translation of Book I from online, in addition to III in the Zinn translation we’re all looking at. Do you have II in English and/or Latin?

    Finally, Scott – I’m interested in hearing more about your last two paragraphs. What you call his “rhetorical helps” I call his mysterianism – in brief the view that it is reasonable that we lack any understandable doctrine of the Trinity. This is in tension with his being, ala Rea, a constitution theorist. So I guess I’d like to see a definition of Richard’s CLT, as well as the texts which contain that CLT.

Comments are closed.